----
FOREWORD: THE DARK MATTER OF VIOLENCE, OR, PUTTING TERROR IN PERSPECTIVE
Slavoj Žižek
----
From time to time, a book appears about which we can say: we were not waiting merely for a book like this; this is the book we were waiting for. Sophie Wahnichâs In Defence of the Terror is such a rare book: it cuts into the very heart of todayâs ethico-political predicament. How can a book about the French Revolution do this?
When, in 1953, Zhou En Lai, the Chinese premier, was in Geneva for the peace negotiations to end the Korean war, a French journalist asked him what he thought about the French Revolution; Chou replied: âIt is still too early to tell.â The events of 1990 proved him spectacularly right: with the disintegration of the âpeopleâs democraciesâ, the struggle for the historical place of the French Revolution flared up again. The liberal revisionists tried to impose the notion that the demise of communism in 1989 occurred at exactly the right moment: it marked the end of the era which began in 1789, the final failure of the statist-revolutionary model which first entered the scene with the Jacobins.
Nowhere is the dictum âevery history is a history of the presentâ more true than in the case of the French Revolution: its historiographical reception has always closely mirrored the twists and turns of later political struggles. The identifying mark of all kinds of conservatives is a predictably flat rejection: the French Revolution was a catastrophe from its very beginning. The product of the godless modern mind, it is at the same time to be interpreted as Godâs judgement on humanityâs wicked ways â so its traces should of course be kicked over as thoroughly as possible. The typical liberal attitude is a more differentiated one: its formula is â1789 without 1793â. In short, what the sensitive liberals want is a decaffeinated revolution, a revolution which does not smell of a revolution. François Furet proposed another liberal approach: he tried to deprive the French Revolution of its status as the founding event of modern democracy, relegating it to a historical anomaly. In short, Furetâs aim was to de-eventalize the French Revolution: it is no longer (as for a tradition stemming from Kant and Hegel) the defining moment of modernity, but a local accident with no global significance, one conditioned by the specifically French tradition of absolute monarchy. Jacobin state centralism is only possible, then, against the background of the âLâétat câest moiâ of Louis XIV. There was a historical necessity to assert the modern principles of personal freedom, etc., but â as the English example demonstrates â the same could have been much more effectively achieved in a more peaceful way . . . Radicals are, on the contrary, possessed by what Alain Badiou called the âpassion of the Realâ: if you say A â equality, human rights and freedoms â then you should not shirk its consequences but instead gather the courage to say B â the terror needed to really defend and assert A.
Both liberal and conservative critics of the French Revolution present it as a founding event of modern âtotalitarianismâ: the taproot of all the worst evils of the twentieth century â the Holocaust, the Gulag, up to the 9/11 attacks â is to be sought in the Jacobin âReign of Terrorâ. The perpetrators of Jacobin crimes are either denounced as bloodthirsty monsters, or, in a more nuanced approach, one admits that they were personally honest and pure, but then adds that this very feature made their fanaticism all the more dangerous. The conclusion is thus the well-known cynical wisdom: better corruption than ethical purity, better a direct lust for power than obsession with oneâs mission. 1
Wahnichâs book systematically undermines this predominant doxa . In a detailed
Jim DeFelice
Blake Northcott
Shan
Carolyn Hennesy
Heather Webber
Tara Fox Hall
Michel Faber
Paul Torday
Rachel Hollis
Cam Larson